James C. Scott, “Practical Knowledge”

Mētis: The Contours of Practical Knowledge

1.     Comparing forms of knowledge embedded in local experience with moral general, abstract knowledge deployed by states or bureaucracies and their technical agencies.

2.     Example:  Squanto:  plant corn when the oaks leaves are the size of a squirrel’s eye.

a)     Practical knowledge of this sort can be translated into more universalistic, scientific terms (but is that useful or practical?)

3.     Mētis: indigenous technical knowledge, fold wisdom, practical skills, judgment-about-particulars, cunning, cunning intelligence, ability to adapt to a constantly shifting situation and craft successful strategies for facing them

a)     Skills that require adapting to a capricious physical environment

b)    The acquired knowledge of how to sail, fly a kite, fish, shear sheep, drive a car, ride a bicycle, build a house, play a violin (and tune it constantly and still play it if a string breaks)

c)     Hand-eye coordination, capacity to “read the waves, the win, or the road and make the proper adjustments”

d)    Difficult to teach apart from doing the activity (coaching, not didactic teaching or reading books; apprenticeship) — practice makes perfect

e)     Some people get the hang of a skill pretty quickly, still, long experience of many situations is generally better

f)     Examples:  Firefighters, rescue squads, paramedics, mine-disaster teams, doctors in hospital emergency rooms, crews that repair downed electrical lines, teams that extinguish fires in oil fields, farmers:  there are ‘rules of thumb’ that apply, but half the battle is knowing which rule of thumb to apply in which order and when to throw the book away and improvise (cf. Sully)

4.     Mētis: relation of people to environment; relation of people to other people

a)     Interacting with others socially (reading them, responding to their cues)

b)    Interacting with others in competition (boxing, fencing, basketball, football)

c)     Team dynamics

d)    War, diplomacy: What can we control?  What can we not control?

e)     All but defies being communicated in written or oral form apart from actual practice

5.     Definition, Description of Mētis:

a)     Most applicable to broadly similar but never precisely identical situations requiring a quick and practiced adaptation that becomes almost second nature to the practitioner

b)    May involve rules of thumb, but such rules are largely acquired through practice and a developed feel or knack for strategy

c)     Resists simplification into deductive principles which can successfully be transmitted through book learning because the environments in which it is exercised are so complex and non-repeatable that formal procedures of rational decision making are impossible to apply [which doesn’t make it irrational, merely not deductively rational; it lacks mathematical certitude]

 The Art of the Locality

1.     Knowing how and when to apply rules of thumb in a concrete situation is the essence of mētis because the situations where it is needed are mutable, indeterminate (some facts are unknown) and particular

2.     Example:  work of the harbor pilot, whose experience is locally superior to the general rules of navigation (or navigation out on the open seas)

3.     Mark Twain: Navigating on the Mississippi

4.     Local guides

5.     The practice and experience reflected in mētis is almost always local or particular

6.     Long experience with different materials will have the effect of making such adjustments quasi-automatic. 

7.     Each loom or potter’s wheel.  Each guitar or violin.  Each piano.  Each type of wood or clay.  Various types of paint.

8.     While something can be said about forestry, revolution, urban planning, agriculture, and rural settlement in general (and dealing with people), this will take us only so far in understanding this forest, this revolution, this battle, this farm, this company, this child.  The more general the rules, the more they require in the way of translation if they are to be locally successful.

9.     The rule of thumb is akin to formal grammar, whereas mētis is more like actual speech.  A knowledge of the rules of speech by themselves is compatible with a complete inability to speak intelligible sentences.  The assertion that the rules of grammar are derivative of the practice of actual speech is nearer to the truth. [How about rules of human conduct?  Rules as rules that virtuous people have learned.  But you would need to become one of them to (a) understand them fully and (b) be able to apply them properly.

10.  Best learned by daily practice and experience.  Socialized to a trade = so too to a way of life. 

11.  Any formula that excludes or suppresses the experience, knowledge, and adaptability of mētis risks incoherence and failure.

12.  But note:  This is NOT relativism.  You are not saying, “I want to do sailing my way” or “I want to do carpentry my way.”  If you turn your sails a certain way, you will capsize.  If you treat the wood a certain way, it will break.  If you don’t line up the bricks a certain way, the wall will fall down.  You are mastering a craft, a tradition of practices that has been shown to be effective.  Will there need to be modifications to fit changed circumstances?  Yes.  But this is reapplying the general principles to new situations.  I may have an engine instead of a sail, but I still don’t want to turn the boat sideways in heavy waves.

13.  Question: Can machines (or computers) take away the need for mētis?  (Say, for example, auto-pilot systems in airplanes?)

The Relation with Episteme and Techne

1.     Deduction; scientific: Is this knowledge useless?  No. It has an important role to play, but we can’t expect it to make up our mind for us.

2.     Knowledge of rules AND knowledge of particulars — broad experience

3.     Scientific knowledge vs. scientific discovery:  the necessity of making judgments

4.     Scientific knowledge:  impersonal, universal, and completely impervious to context vs. mētis involving situations which are transient, shifting, disconcerting, and ambiguous, situations which do not lend themselves to precise measurement, exact calculation, or formal deductive, analytic logic.

5.     A recurrent theme (and dream) of Western science has been the attempt to formulate systems of knowledge in order to bracket uncertainty and thereby permit the kind of logical deductive rigor possessed by Euclidean geometry:  get the data, gather the evidence, do the math, make the deductions, get THE answer

6.     Even chance (probability), it is assumed, can be brought into mathematical precision

7.     Formulas of efficiency, production functions, and rational action are specifiable only when the ends sought are simple, sharply defined, and hence measurable.

8.     The problem, as Aristotle recognized, is that certain practical choices cannot “even in principle, be adequately and completely captured in a system of universal rules.  Navigation and medicine:  responsiveness, improvisation, and skillful, successive approximations are required.

Practical Knowledge Versus Scientific Explanation

1.     Note the valuable knowledge that high-modernist schemes deprive themselves of when they simply impose their plans as “scientific” (nothing but “scientific” discourse is acceptable)

2.     Vernacular measures were often designed to achieve a local purpose or to express an important feature rather than to accommodate some universal unit of measurement.

3.     Such measures apparently often conveyed more information than an abstract measure could and more information that was locally relevant.

4.     The litmus test for mētis is practical success.  Did the navigator make the trip safely?  Did the medicine cure the wound?  If a technique works effectively and repeatedly for the purpose intended, the practitioners of mētis do not pause long to ask why and how it worked, to define the precise mechanism of cause and effect.

5.     Hence innovations will often run out ahead of scientific cause and effect reasoning.  Innovations will typically represent a recombination of existing elements; farmers did not invent the tractor to solve their problems of traction power.  By the same token, the recombination of practical knowledge has often produced complex techniques that work admirably but that science has not (yet?) understood.

6.     The power of practical knowledge depends on an exceptionally close and astute observation of the environment.

7.     By people who have a vital, direct stake in the results of close observation (skin in the game).

8.     The value of having people who live year in and year out, day in and day out “in the field of observation.”  He or she will likely know things that neither an absentee cultivator nor a research scientist would ever notice.

9.     Member of a community that serves as a living, oral reference library for observations, practices, and experiments — a body of knowledge that an individual could never amass alone.

10.  How often local knowledge, trial and error, produced practical solutions without benefit of scientific method.

11.  Combination of passionate interest, close observation, and large numbers of amateur specialists trying different possibilities, all willing to learn from one another.

12.  Mētis might be replaced by deeper knowledge or at least fostered by it, but by the same token, mētis is the mode of reasoning most appropriate to complex material and social tasks where the uncertainties are so daunting that we must trust our (experienced) intuition and feel our way.

13.  Water management in Japan:  No more is attempted than Nature has already done in the region.  The engineer recognizes that he is dealing with an art of one valley.  Each prudent, small step, based on prior experience, yields new and not completely predictable effects that become the point of departure for the next step  Virtually any complex task involving many variables whose values and interactions cannot be accurately forecast belongs to this genre: building a house, repairing a car, perfecting a new jet engine, surgically repairing a knee, or farming a plot of land

14.  Especially where the interactions involve not just material environment but social interaction as well — building and populating new villages or cities, organizing a revolutionary seizure of power or reorganizing farming.

15.  Communicating not merely (perhaps not primarily) the blueprint for a new house, but an understanding of the experience that made it at all possible to build under various circumstances:  here are the problems we encountered and things we didn’t expect and things that really helped

Learning Beyond the Book

1.     Breaking down the process into more manageable, “agile” steps

2.     But note, this does not mean that a novice can take over: only someone with wide experience will be able to interpret the results of and reactions to an initial step in order to determine the next step.

3.     With more experience and wisdom, the repertoire of responses would be larger, their judgment in reading the environment surer, their sense of what surprises might await them more accurate.

4.     This is hard to teach: it is something that comes with long practice and experience

5.     Any experienced practitioner of a skill or craft will develop a large repertoire of moves, visual judgments, a sense of touch, or a discriminating gestalt for assessing the work as well as a range of accurate intuitions born of experience that defy being communicated apart from practice: the studied, “practical” eye [cf. Malcom Gladwell,
“Blink”]

6.     ‘Heat the oil until it is almost smoking.’

They Dynamism and Plasticity of Mētis

1.     “Traditional peoples” will embrace techniques that solve vital problems. 

2.     A certain understanding of science, modernity, and development has so successfully structured the dominant discourse that all other kinds of knowledge are regarded as backward, static traditions, as old wives’ tales and superstitions. 

3.     High modernism needed this “other,” this dark twin, in order to rhetorically present itself as the antidote to backwardness.

4.     Mētis, far from being rigid and monolithic, is plastic, local, and divergent.  It is in the fact the idiosyncrasies of metis, its contextualness, and its fragmentation that make it so permeable, so open to new ideas.

5.     No traditional way of behavior, no traditional skill ever remains fixed.  It history is one of continual change.  The changes are likely to be small and gradual (incrementalism) rather than sudden and discontinuous. (Unless a tradition becomes static and dead.

The Social Context of Mētis and its Destruction

1.     What is needed is a social context in which knowledge is discovered and maintained in the context of lifelong observation and a relatively stable, multigenerational community that routinely exchanges and preserves knowledge of this kind.

2.     Social conditions necessary for the reproduction of comparable practical knowledge.

a)     Community of interest

b)    Accumulated information

c)     Ongoing experimentation

d)    What kind of social structures (and physical structures) allow this?

3.     Two of the great ironies of metis:

a)     Metis is not democratically distributed; depends on the social structure of the society whether it gets shared and expanded

b)    However plastic and receptive metis is, some forms of it seem to depend on key elements of preindustrial life for their elaboration and transmission

4.     The loss of metis:  sometimes for the purposes of simplification of life. But it would be a serious error to believe that the destruction of metis was merely the inadvertent and necessary by-product of economic progress.  As a ‘project,’ it is the object of constant initiatives which are never entirely successful, for no forms of production or social life can be made to work by formulas alone — that is, without metis.  The logic animating the project, however, is one of control and appropriation, administrative order and fiscal appropriation, discipline and profit.

5.     Efficiency and control:  Who profits?

a)     The crucial advantage of the factory from the boss’s point of view as that he could more directly fix the hours and the intensity of the work and control the raw materials.

b)    The genius of modern mass-production methods: destroying metis and turning a resistant, quasi-autonomous artisan population into more suitable units, or “factory hands” with greater clarity. 

c)     Under scientific management … the managers assume … the burdens of gathering together all of the traditional knowledge which in the past has been possessed by the workmen and then of classifying, tabulating, and reducing this knowledge to rules, laws, formulae….  Thus all of the planning which under the old system was done by the workmen must of necessity under the new system be done by management in accordance with the law of science.

d)    In the factory, only the factory manager had the knowledge and command of the whole process, and the worker was reduced to the execution of a small, often minute, part of the overall process. 

e)     And yet, metis cannot be completely engineered out.

f)     More than one plantation sector has made up what it lacked in efficiency by using its political clout to secure subsidies, price supports, and monopoly privileges.

The Case Against Imperial Knowledge

1.     What has provide to be truly dangerous to us and to our environment is the combination of the universalist pretensions of epistemic knowledge and authoritarian social engineering.

2.     Universalist claims seem inherent in the way in which rationalist knowledge is pursued.  Is there a door in this epistemic edifice through which metis or practical knowledge could enter on its own terms?  Hard to see how. It is this imperialism that is troubling. 

3.     The great failure of rationalism is not its recognition of technical knowledge, but its failure to recognize any other. 

-       Consider:  the “science” of medicine vs. “ethical considerations” which are “opinions” and which can be handled in a weekend seminar

4.     Authoritarian, high-modernist states in the grip of a self-evident (and usually half-baked) social theory have done irreparable damage to human communities and individuals.

5.     The danger was compounded when leaders came to believe that the people were a “blank piece of paper” on which the new regime could write.

6.     Each generation, indeed each administration, shall see unrolled before it the blank sheet of infinite possibility, and if by chance this tabula rasa has been defaced by the irrational scribblings of tradition-ridden ancestors, then the first task of the rationalist must be to scrub it clean.


* The danger: Thinking we can (and then seeking to) remake the world and mankind (other people) in our own image.

As opposed to: Remaking Ourselves into God’s image (Acting toward God and God’s law as “Father” by becoming like “the Son” — becoming “like Christ” (selfless gift of self) — made possible because we are animated by God’s Spirit. We are animated (in our “spirit”) by the Love shared between the Father and the Son.  We participate in the divine love.

-       What drives the machine?  What spirit breathes life into the organism? 

-       I care enough to observe closely and in an unbiased manner.  I am attentive to the world as it is and to other people as they are — noticing both positive things and problems.

-       Getting over my self-interested or selfish biases.

-       Having the humility to discipline myself to being mentored in a tradition

-       Admitting mistakes and learning from them

-       Realizing that “freedom of excellence” comes with discipline, self-awareness, care, concern, attention, openness, and a constant search for greater insight and wisdom

            -       Flourishing is not simply my making myself according to my wishes or whims.  Excellence comes from working with and for others, in accord with the rhythms and reality of the world as it actually is.  I don’t create it; I discover it and act accordingly.